basic constructions:
strong axioms
further
This is Part III of an exposition by Todd Trimble on ETCS.
See also
Part I. ZFC and ETCS
Part II. ETCS: Internalizing the logic
After a long hiatus, I’d like to renew the discussion of axiomatic categorical set theory, more specifically the Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets (ETCS). Last time I blogged about this, I made some initial forays into “internalizing logic” in ETCS, and described in broad brushstrokes how to use that internal logic to derive a certain amount of the structure one associates with a category of sets. Today I’d like to begin applying some of the results obtained there to the problem of constructing colimits in a category satisfying the ETCS axioms (an ETCS category, for short).
(If you’re just joining us now, and you already know some of the jargon, an ETCS category is a well-pointed topos that satisfies the axiom of choice and with a natural numbers object. We are trying to build up some of the elementary theory of such categories from scratch, with a view toward foundations of mathematics.)
But let’s see — where were we? Since it’s been a while, I was tempted to review the philosophy behind this undertaking (why one would go to all the trouble of setting up a categories-based alternative to ZFC, when time-tested ZFC is able to express virtually all of present-day mathematics on the basis of a reasonably short list of axioms?). But in the interest of time and space, I’ll confine myself to a few remarks.
As we said, a chief difference between ZFC and ETCS resides in how ETCS treats the issue of membership. In ZFC, membership is a global binary relation: we can take any two “sets” and ask whether . Whereas in ETCS, membership is a relation between entities of different sorts: we have “sets” on one side and “elements” on another, and the two are not mixed ( e.g., elements are not themselves considered sets).
Further, and far more radical: in ETCS the membership relation is a function, that is, an element “belongs” to only one set at a time. We can think of this as “declaring” how we are thinking of an element, that is, declaring which set (or which type) an element is being considered as belonging to. (In the jargon, ETCS is a typed theory.) This reflects a general and useful philosophic principle: that elements in isolation are considered inessential, that what counts are the aggregates or contexts in which elements are organized and interrelated. For instance, the numeral “2” in isolation has no meaning; what counts is the context in which we think of it ( qua rational number or qua complex number, etc.). Similarly the set of real numbers has no real sense in isolation; what counts is which category we view it in.
I believe it is reasonable to grant this principle a foundational status, but: rigorous adherence to this principle completely changes the face of what set theory looks like. If elements “belong” only to one set at a time, how then do we even define such basic concepts as subsets and intersections? These are some of the issues we discussed last time.
There are other significant differences between ZFC and ETCS: stylistically, or in terms of presentation, ZFC is more “top-down” and ETCS is more “bottom-up”. For example, in ZFC, one can pretty much define a subset by writing down a first-order formula in the language; the comprehension (or separation) axiom scheme is a mighty sledgehammer that takes care of the rest. In the axioms of ETCS, there is no such sledgehammer: the closest thing one has to a comprehension scheme in the ETCS axioms is the power set axiom (a single axiom, not an axiom scheme). However, in the formal development of ETCS, one derives a comprehension scheme as one manually constructs the internal logic, in stages, using the simple tools of adjunctions and universal properties. We started doing some of that in our last post. So: with ZFC it’s more as if you can just hop in the car and go; with ETCS you build the car engine from smaller parts with your bare hands, but in the process you become an expert mechanic, and are not so rigidly attached to a particular make and model ( e.g., much of the theory is built just on the axioms of a topos, which allows a lot more semantic leeway than one has with ZF).
But, in all fairness, that is perhaps the biggest obstacle to learning ETCS: at the outset, the tools available [mainly, the idea of a universal property] are quite simple but parsimonious, and one has to learn how to build some set-theoretic and logical concepts normally taken as “obvious” from the ground up. (Talk about “foundations”!) On the plus side, by building big logical machines from scratch, one gains a great deal of insight into the inner workings of logic, with a corresponding gain in precision and control and modularity when one would like to use these developments to design, say, automated deduction systems (where there tend to be strong advantages to using type-theoretic frameworks).
Note to the experts. Most textbook treatments of the formal development of topos theory (as for example Mac Lane–Moerdijk) are efficient but highly technical, involving for instance the slice theorem for toposes and, in the construction of colimits, recourse to Beck’s theorem in monad theory applied to the double power-set monad [following the elegant construction of Par]. The very abstract nature of this style of argumentation (which in the application of Beck’s theorem expresses ideas of fourth-order set theory and higher) is no doubt partly responsible for the somewhat fearsome reputation of topos theory.
In these notes I take a much less efficient but much more elementary approach, based on an arrangement of ideas which I hope can be seen as “natural” from the point of view of naive set theory. I learned of this approach from Myles Tierney, who was my PhD supervisor, and who with Bill Lawvere co-founded elementary topos theory, but I am not aware of any place where the details of this approach have been written up before now. I should also mention that the approach taken here is not as “purist” as many topos theorists might want; for example, here and there I take advantage of the strong extensionality axiom of ETCS to simplify some arguments.
We begin with the easy observation that a terminal category, i.e., a category with just one object and one morphism (the identity), satisfies all the ETCS axioms. Ditto for any category equivalent to (where every object is terminal). Such boring ETCS categories are called degenerate; obviously our interest is in the structure of nondegenerate ETCS categories.
Let be an ETCS category (see here for the ETCS axioms). Objects of are generally called “sets”, and morphisms are generally called “functions” or “maps”.
Proposition 0. If an ETCS category is a preorder, then is degenerate.
Proof. Recall that a preorder is a category in which there is at most one morphism for any two objects . Every morphism in a preorder is vacuously monic. If there is a nonterminal set , then the monic to any terminal set defines a subset distinct from the subset defined by , thus giving (in an ETCS category) distinct classifying maps , contradicting the preorder assumption. Therefore all objects are terminal.
Assume from now on that is a nondegenerate ETCS category.
Proposition 1. There are at least two truth values, i.e., two elements , in .
Proof. By proposition 0, there exist sets and two distinct functions . By the axiom of strong extensionality, there exists such that . The equalizer of the pair is then a proper subset of , and therefore there are at least two distinct elements .
Proposition 2. There are at most two truth values ; equivalently, there are at most two subsets of .
Proof. If are distinct subsets of , then either or , say the former. Then and are distinct subsets, with distinct classifying maps . By strong extensionality, there exists distinguishing these classifying maps. Because is terminal, we then infer and , so as subsets of , and in that case only can be a proper subset of .
By Propositions 1 and 2, there is a unique proper subset of the terminal object . Let denote this subset. Its domain may be called an “empty set”; by the preceding proposition, it has no proper subsets. The classifying map of is the truth value we call “false”.
Proposition 3. 0 is an initial object, i.e., for any there exists a unique function .
Proof. Uniqueness: if are maps, then their equalizer , which is monic, must be an isomorphism since 0 has no proper subsets. Therefore . Existence: there are monos
where is “global truth” (classifying the subset ) on and is the “singleton mapping ” on , defined as the classifying map of the diagonal map (last time we saw is monic). Take their pullback. The component of the pullback parallel to is a mono which again is an isomorphism, whence we get a map using the other component of the pullback.
Remark. For the “purists”, an alternative construction of the initial set 0 that avoids use of the strong extensionality axiom is to define the subset to be “the intersection all subsets of ”. Formally, one takes the extension of the map
where the first arrow represents the class of all subsets of , and the second is the internal intersection operator defined at the end of our last post. Using formal properties of intersection developed later, this intersection has no proper subsets, and then the proof of proposition 3 carries over verbatim.
Corollary 1. For any , the set is initial.
Proof. By cartesian closure, maps are in bijection with maps of the form , and there is exactly one of these since 0 is initial.
Corollary 2. If there exists , then is initial.
Proof. The composite of followed by is , and followed by is also an identity since is initial by Corollary 1. Hence is isomorphic to an initial object .
By Corollary 2, for any object the arrow is vacuously monic, hence defines a subset.
Proposition 4. If , then there exists an element .
Proof. Under the assumption, has at least two distinct subsets: and . By strong extensionality, their classifying maps are distinguished by some element .
One of the major goals in this post is to construct finite coproducts in an ETCS category. As in ordinary set theory, we will construct these as disjoint unions. This means we need to discuss unions first; as should be expected by now, in ETCS unions are considered locally, i.e., we take unions of subsets of a given set. So, let be subsets.
To define the union , the idea is to take the intersection of all subsets containing and . That is, we apply the internal intersection operator (constructed last time ),
Remark. Remember that in ETCS we are using generalized elements: really means a function over some domain , which in turn classifies a subset . On the other hand, the here is a subset . How then do we interpret the condition “”? We first pull back over to the domain (that is, we form the composite ) and consider the condition that this is bounded above by . (We will write , thinking of the left side as constant over .) Externally, in terms of subsets, this corresponds to the condition .
We need to construct the subsets . In ZFC, we could construct those subsets by applying the comprehension axiom scheme, but the axioms of ETCS have no such blanket axiom scheme. (In fact, as we said earlier, much of the work on “internalizing logic” goes to show that in ETCS, we instead derive a comprehension scheme!) However, one way of defining subsets in ETCS is by taking loci of equations; here, we express the condition , more pedantically or , as the equation
where the right side is the predicate “true over ”.
Thus we construct the subset of via the pullback:
Let me take a moment to examine what this diagram means exactly. Last time we constructed an internal implication operator
and now, in the pullback diagram above, what we are implicitly doing is lifting this to an operator
The easy and cheap way of doing this is to remember the isomorphism we used last time to uncover the cartesian closed structure, and apply this to
to define . This map classifies a certain subset of , which I’ll just write down (leaving it as an exercise which involves just chasing the relevant definitions):
Remark. Similarly we can define a meet operator by exponentiating the internal meet . It is important to know that the general Heyting algebra identities which we established last time for lift to the corresponding identities for the operators on . Ultimately this rests on the fact that the functor , being a right adjoint, preserves products, and therefore preserves any algebraic identity which can be expressed as a commutative diagram of operations between such products.
Hence, for the fixed subset (classified by ), the operator
classifies the subset
Finally, in the pullback diagram above, we are pulling back the operator against . But, from last time, that was exactly the method we used to construct universal quantification. That is, given a subset
we defined to be the pullback of along .
Putting all this together, the pullback diagram above expresses the definition
that one would expect “naively”.
Now that all the relevant constructions are in place, we show that is the join of and in the poset . There is nothing intrinsically difficult about this, but as we are still in the midst of constructing the internal logic, we will have to hunker down and prove some logic things normally taken for granted or zipped through without much thought. For example, the internal intersection operator was defined with the help of internal universal quantification, and we will need to establish some formal properties of that.
Here is a useful general principle for doing internal logic calculations. Let be the classifying map of a subset , and let be a function. Then the composite classifies the subset
so that one has the general identity . In passing back and forth between the external and internal viewpoints, the general principle is to try to render “complicated” functions into a form which one can more easily recognize. For lack of a better term, I’ll call this the “pullback principle”.
Lemma 1. Given a relation and a constant , there is an inclusion
as subsets of . (In traditional logical syntax, this says that for any element ,
as predicates over elements . This is the type of thing that ordinarily “goes without saying”, but which we actually have to prove here!)
Proof. As we recalled above, was defined to be , the pullback of global truth along the classifying map . Hold that thought.
Let
be the map which classifies the subset . Equivalently, this is the map
under the canonical isomorphisms , . Intuitively, this maps , i.e., plugs an element into an element .
Using the adjunction of cartesian closure, the composite
transforms to the composite
so by the pullback principle, classifies .
Equivalently,
Also, as subsets of , we have the inclusion
[this just says that belongs to the subset classified by , or equivalently that is in the subset ]. Applying the pullback operation to (2), and comparing to (1), Lemma 1 follows.
Lemma 2. If as subsets of , then .
Proof. From the last post, we have an adjunction:
for any subset of . So it suffices to show . But
where the first inclusion follows from .
Next, recall from the last post that the internal intersection of was defined by interpreting the following formula on the right:
Lemma 3. If , then .
Proof. classifies the subset , i.e., is identified with the predicate in the argument , so by hypothesis as predicates on . Internal implication is contravariant in the argument [see the following remark], so
Remark. The contravariance of , that is, the fact that implies , is a routine exercise using the adjunction [discussed last time] if and only if
Indeed, we have
where the first inequality follows from the hypothesis , and the second follows from . By the adjunction, the inequality implies .
Theorem 1. For subsets of , the subset is an upper bound of and , i.e., .
Proof. It suffices to prove that , since then we need only apply Lemma 3 to the trivially true inclusion
to infer , and similarly . (Actually, we need only show . We’ll do that first, and then show full equality.)
The condition we want,
is, by the adjunction , equivalent to
which, by a - adjunction, is equivalent to
as subsets of . So we just have to prove (1). At this point we recall, from our earlier analysis, that
Using the adjunction , as in the proof of Lemma 2, we have
which shows that the left side of (1) is contained in
where the last inclusion uses another - adjunction. Thus we have established (1) and therefore also the inclusion
Now we prove the opposite inclusion
that is to say
Here we just use Lemma 1, applied to the particular element : we see that the left side of is contained in
which collapses to , since . This completes the proof.
Theorem 2. is the least upper bound of , i.e., if is a subset containing both and , then .
Proof. We are required to show that
Again, we just apply Lemma 1 to the particular element : the left-hand side of the claimed inclusion is contained in
but since is true by hypothesis (is globally true as a predicate on the implicit variable ), this last subset collapses to
which completes the proof.
Theorems 1 and 2 show that for any set , the external poset admits joins. One may go on to show (just on the basis of the topos axioms) that as in the case of meets, the global external operation of taking joins is natural in , so that by the Yoneda principle, it is classified by an internal join operation
namely, the map which classifies the union of the subsets
and this operation satisfies all the expected identities. In short, carries an internal Heyting algebra structure, as does for any set .
We will come back to this point later, when we show (as a consequence of strong extensionality) that is actually an internal Boolean algebra.
Next, we construct coproducts just as we do in ordinary set theory: as disjoint unions. Letting be sets (objects in an ETCS category), a disjoint union of and is a pair of monos
whose intersection is empty, and whose union or join in is all of . We will show that disjoint unions exist and are essentially unique, and that they satisfy the universal property for coproducts. We will use the notation for a disjoint union.
Theorem 3. A disjoint union of and exists.
It’s enough to embed disjointly into some set , since the union of the two monos in would then be the requisite . The idea now is that if a disjoint union or coproduct exists, then there’s a canonical isomorphism . Since the singleton map
is monic, one thus expects to be able to embed and disjointly into . Since we can easily work out how all this goes in ordinary naive set theory, we just write out the formulas and hope it works out in ETCS.
In detail, define to be
where is the singleton mapping and classifies ; similarly, define to be
Clearly and are monic, so to show disjointness we just have to show that their pullback is empty. But their pullback is isomorphic to the cartesian product of the pullbacks of the diagrams
so it would be enough to show that each (or just one) of these two pullbacks is empty, let’s say the first.
Suppose given a map which makes the square
commute. Using the pullback principle, the map classifies
which is just the empty subset. This must be the same subset as classified by (where is the diagonal), which by the pullback principle is
An elementary calculation shows this to be the equalizer of the pair of maps
So this equalizer is empty. But notice that equalizes this pair of maps. Therefore we have a map . By Corollary 2 above, we infer . This applies to the case where is the pullback, so the pullback is empty, as was to be shown.
Theorem 4. Any two disjoint unions of are canonically isomorphic.
Suppose is a disjoint union. Define a map
where classifies the subset , and classifies the subset . Applying the pullback principle, the composite classifies
which is easily seen to be the diagonal on . Hence . On the other hand, classifies the subset
which is empty because and are disjoint embeddings, so . Similar calculations yield
Putting all this together, we conclude that and , where and were defined in the proof of Theorem 3.
Next, we show that is monic. If not, then by strong extensionality, there exist distinct elements for which ; therefore, and . By the pullback principle, these equations say (respectively)
If , then both factor through the mono . However, since is monic, this would imply that , contradiction. Therefore . By similar reasoning, . Therefore
where is the negation operator. But then . And since is the union by assumption, must be the top element , whence is the bottom element 0. This contradicts the assumption that the topos is nondegenerate. Thus we have shown that must be monic.
The argument above shows that is an upper bound of and in . It follows that the join constructed in Theorem 3 is contained in , and hence can be regarded as the join of and in . But is their join in by assumption of being a disjoint union, so the containment must be an equality. The proof is now complete.
Theorem 5. The inclusions , exhibit as the coproduct of and .
Let , be given functions. Then we have monos
Now the operation certainly preserves finite meets, and also preserves finite joins because it is left adjoint to . Therefore this operation preserves disjoint unions; we infer that the monos
exhibit as a disjoint union of . Composing the monos of (1) and (2), we have disjoint embeddings of and in . Using Theorem 4, is isomorphic to the join of these embeddings; this means we have an inclusion
whose restriction to yields and whose restriction to yields . Hence extends and . It is the unique extension, for if there were two extensions , then their equalizer would be an upper bound of in , contradicting the fact that is the least upper bound. This completes the proof.
I think that’s enough for one day. I will continue to explore the categorical structure and logic of ETCS next time.
Last revised on December 12, 2021 at 05:07:11. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.